ABSTRACT

Coalition theory is one of the fields that has extensively benefited from formal modelling in political science. Since the publication of William Riker’s (1962) seminal book, a variety of coalition models has been developed to explain government formation and breakdown. Nevertheless, despite the diversity of models, the literature seems to judge their predictability solely in terms of empirical tests, usually deriving hypotheses from their propositions and testing via statistics. In this work, I survey classical and more recent formal models in coalition theory, demonstrating how they serve different purposes. I build a taxonomy of models that acknowledges these purposes, and, more importantly, the roles they play in building explanations about coalitions. I identify three types of models: conceptual models, whose conceptual and theoretical value relies on the mathematical deductions entailed in the model; quasi-conceptual models, which formalise explanations of regularities in the real world; and extrapolative models, which allow for an empirical test of formal models via a variety of statistical methods. All of these types of models coexist, generating explanations and setting research agendas.

Keywords: coalition models, taxonomy of formal models, Government formation, Government breakdown.

RESUMEN

Las teorías de las coaliciones son uno de los campos que se ha beneficiado enormemente de modelos formales en la ciencia política. Desde la publicación del libro fundamental de William Riker (1962) se han desarrollado una variedad de modelos de coalición para explicar la formación y el colapso del Gobierno. Sin embargo, a pesar de la diversidad de modelos, la literatura parece juzgar su predictibilidad basándose únicamente en los test empíricos, usualmente derivando las hipótesis a partir de las premisas de los modelos y probándolos a través de modelos estadísticos. En este trabajo, examino modelos formales clásicos y otros más recientes en la teoría de coalición, demostrando como sirven para diferentes propósitos. Construyo una taxonomía de los modelos que reconoce estas funciones, y lo más importante, los papeles que juegan en la construcción de explicaciones sobre coaliciones. Identifico tres tipos de modelos: conceptuales, cuyo valor conceptual y teórico reside en las deducciones matemáticas del modelo; modelos cuasi-conceptuales, que formalizan explicaciones sobre regularidades en el mundo real, y modelos extrapolativos, que permiten realizar pruebas empíricas de los modelos formales por vía de una variedad de métodos estadísticos. Estos tres tipos de modelos coexisten, generando explicaciones y definiendo agendas de investigación.

Palabras clave: modelos de coalición, taxonomía de modelos formales, formación del Gobierno, colapso del Gobierno.

Citation / Cómo citar este artículo: Lenine, E. (2019). Explaining coalitions: A taxonomy of formal models of Government formation and breakdown. Revista Española de Ciencia Política, 49, 43-‍62. Doi: https://doi.org/10.21308/recp.49.02

CONTENTS

  1. Abstract
  2. Resumen
  3. INTRODUCTION
  4. CONCEPTUAL MODELS: SETTING THE FOUNDATIONS OF COALITION THEORY
  5. QUASI-CONCEPTUAL MODELS OF COALITION FORMATION: EXPLAINING REGULARITIES
  6. TESTING COALITION MODELS
  7. ASSESSMENT
  8. CONCLUSION
  9. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
  10. Notes
  11. References

INTRODUCTION[up]

As an academic endeavour, coalition theory mobilizes concepts and models from different fields in political science. One cannot think of coalitions without resorting to the language of party competition, electoral systems, veto players and ministerial cabinets. Indeed, coalitions are all about putting these pieces together. Game theory and spatial models constitute the essence of modelling in coalition theory, answering questions about the mechanisms underlying the formation, duration and breakdown of governments.

These models have become pervasive in the literature on coalition theory. The current state of affairs reveals an immense accumulation of knowledge in terms of mathematical models, conceptual analyses and empirical tests. Rational choice models play a crucial role in this process, by setting agendas, framing research questions, advancing concepts and explaining empirical regularities. They serve distinct purposes, not only the widely-spread view that tends to relate a model’s predictions to an exercise of data-fit. The essence of modelling is the constant search for explanations, the unravelling of mechanisms and the generation of predictions about general phenomena.

In this sense, this article aims to provide an understanding of models that acknowledges the different purposes they are designed for. It departs from the following question: what are the distinguishing characteristics of formal modelling in coalition theory? I argue that coalition models serve different purposes, generating explanations of various kinds and models that should not be judged by the single metric of empirical testability. Formal modelling has been constantly targeted with criticisms along the lines of lack of empirical evidence, but such argument does not tell the whole story about how models tailor explanations. For that models perform a variety of roles on conceptual, and empirical levels, each of which generates understandings about coalition formation and breakdown.

This being said, the novelty of my approach consists in the surveying of classical and recent developments in coalition theory, for it is a field where at least three types of models can be identified: conceptual models, whose conceptual and theoretical value relies on the mathematical deductions entailed in the model; quasi-conceptual models, which formalise explanations of regularities in the real-world; and extrapolative models, which allow for an empirical test of formal models via a variety of statistical methods (regression, multivariate analysis, maximum likelihood estimation etc.). Therefore, I advance the argument that in order to fully grasp the value of coalition models, it has to be acknowledged that each class of model tailors explanations of coalition formation and breakdown in its own fashion. Thus, my goal consists in developing a novel taxonomy of models that identifies the different ways they generate explanation and prediction.

The research agenda on coalition theory thrived after the publication of William Riker’s The Theory of Political Coalitions ( ‍Riker, William H. 1962. The Theory of Political Coalitions. New Haven: Yale University Press.1962), even though much of the spatial modelling was already in place thanks to the works by Harold Hotelling ( ‍Hotelling, Harold. 1929. “Stability in Competition”, Economic Journal, 39 (153): 41-‍57. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2224214.1929), Duncan Black ( ‍Black, Duncan. 1958. The Theory of Committees and Elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.1958) and Anthony Downs ( ‍Downs, Anthony. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper and Row.1957), not to mention earlier works by John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern ( ‍Von Neumann, John and Oskar Morgenstern. 1953. Theory of Games and Economic Behaviour. Princeton: Princeton University Press.1953) on the minimum-winning hypothesis and its posterior test by William Gamson ( ‍Gamson, William. 1961. “A Theory of Coalition Formation”, American Sociological Review, 26 (3): 373-‍382. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2090664.1961) ‍[1]. Riker devised the concept of minimal-winning coalition, which consists of coalitions as large as necessary to ensure winning ( ‍Hindmoor, Andrew and Brad Taylor. 2015. Rational Choice. London: Palgrave. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-137-42744-1.Hindmoor and Taylor, 2015: 85). Politicians see the process of acquiring support and votes as costly, and hence they optimise their actions by guaranteeing precisely the number of votes necessary to approve their proposals. In other words, Riker sees the problem of coalition-formation as an optimisation problem: the equilibrium resides on the optimal point of minimal costs and minimal size.

Riker’s model was intrinsically simple and its main insight rests on the concept of minimum-winning coalition. However, such simplicity could not explain the variation observed in the real world. Some claimed that disequilibrium was more frequent than equilibrium, linking this idea to McKelvey-Schoffield chaos theorem. Riker conceded to this: “Disequilibrium, or the potential that the status quo be upset, is the characteristic feature of politics” ( ‍Riker, William H. 1980. “Implications from the Disequilibrium of Majority Rule for the Study of Institutions”, American Political Science Review, 74 (2): 432-‍446.1980: 443). Yet instead of dismissing the initial model, political scientists and economists have attempted to find causes for disequilibrium and alternative explanations to the variation observed in the real-world ( ‍Dowding, Keith. 1995. “Interpreting Formal Coalition Theory”, in Keith Dowding and Desmond King (eds.), Preferences, Institutions, and Rational Choice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Dowding, 1995: 44-‍48). A myriad of models have been built to understand the role of parties and the formateur ( ‍Bassi, Anna. 2013. “A Model of Endogenous Government Formation”, American Journal of Political Science, 57 (4): 777-‍793. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/ajps.12031.Bassi, 2013;  ‍Bäck, Hannah and Patrick Dumont. 2008. “Making the First Move”, Public Choice, 135 (3-‍4): 353-‍373. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-007-9267-5Bäck and Dumont, 2008;  ‍Diermeier, Daniel and Antonio Merlo. (2004). “An empirical investigation of coalitional bargaining procedures”, Journal of Public Economics, 88 (3-‍4): 783-‍797. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1016/S0047-2727(03)00035-5.Diermeier and Merlo, 2004;  ‍Diermeier, Daniel and Razvan Vlaicu. 2011. “Parties, Coalitions, and the Internal Organization of Legislatures”, American Political Science Review, 105 (2): 359-‍380. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055411000104.Diermeier and Vlaicu, 2011), the process of coalition formation and breakdown ( ‍Ansolabehere, Stephen, James M. Snyder Jr., Aaron B. Strauss and Michael M. Ting. 2005. “Voting Weights and Formateur Advantages in the Formation of Coalition Governments”, American Journal of Political Science, 49 (3): 550-‍563. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2005.00141.x.Ansolabehere et al., 2005;  ‍Giannetti, Daniela and Itai Sened. 2004. “Party Competition and Coalition Formation”, Journal of Theoretical Politics, 16 (4): 483-‍515. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/0951629804046151.Giannetti and Sened, 2004;  ‍Martin, Lanny W. and Randolph T. Stevenson. 2001. “Government Formation in Parliamentary Democracies”, American Journal of Political Science, 45 (1): 33-‍50. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2669358.Martin and Stevenson, 2001,  ‍Martin, Lanny W. and Randolph T. Stevenson. 2010. “The Conditional Impact of Incumbency on Government Formation”, American Political Science Review, 104 (3): 503-‍518. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055410000213.2010;  ‍Martin, Lanny W. and Georg Vanberg. 2005. “Coalition Policymaking and Legislative Review”, American Political Science Review, 99 (1): 93-‍106. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055405051518.Martin and Vanberg, 2005;  ‍Volden, Craig and Clifford J. Carrubba. 2004. “The Formation of Oversized Coalitions in Parliamentary Democracies”, American Journal of Political Science, 48 (3): 521-‍537. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0092-5853.2004.00085.x.Volden and Carrubba, 2004), and the relationship between ministers and coalitions ( ‍Huber, John D. and Cecilia Martinez-Gallardo. 2008. “Replacing Cabinet Ministers: Patterns of Ministerial Stability in Parliamentary Democracies”, American Political Science Review, 102 (2): 169-‍180. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S000305540808012X.Huber and Martinez-Gallardo, 2008;  ‍Laver, Michael and Kenneth Shepsle. 1996. Making and Breaking Governments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625671.Laver and Shepsle, 1996). These models typically address the roles played by prime-ministers, parties, institutional setting, legislative behaviour, ministers etc. The recent institutionalist turn in political science helped to bind these agendas together into a consistent research framework ( ‍Dowding, Keith and Desmond King. 1995. “Introduction”, in Keith Dowding and Desmond King, (eds.), Preferences, Institutions, and Rational Choice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Dowding and King, 1995: 1-‍4;  ‍Dowding, Keith. 1995. “Interpreting Formal Coalition Theory”, in Keith Dowding and Desmond King (eds.), Preferences, Institutions, and Rational Choice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Dowding, 1995: 50-‍55)

Historical institutionalists have also contributed to the theoretical endeavour in coalition theory. By taking a historicist approach to political phenomena, these scholars draw attention to issues of timing and sequencing, and the complex relations between agents and institutions (

Pierson, Paul. 2004. Politics in time. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1515/9781400841080.

Pierson, 2004
,

Pierson, Paul. 2015. “Power and path dependence”, in James Mahoney y Kathleen Thelen (eds.), Advances in Comparative-Historical Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316273104.006.

2015
;

Thelen, Kathleen and James Mahoney. 2015. “Comparative-historical analysis in contemporary political science”, in James Mahoney y Kathleen Thelen (eds.), Advances in Comparative-Historical Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316273104.002.

Thelen and Mahoney, 2015
). In particular, Hacker et al. (

Hacker, Jacob S., Paul Pierson and Kathleen Thelen. 2015. “Drift and conversion: hidden faces of institutional change”, in James Mahoney and Kathleen Thelen (eds.), Advances in Comparative-Historical Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316273104.008.

2015
) analysis of institutional change via drift or conversion offers an interesting epistemology to understand how coalitions may reinterpret institutions to serve their own ends, in a typical bargaining process.

‍[2]
. Nonetheless, instead of following one single theoretical and empirical path, coalition theory is rather an umbrella that covers a myriad of models and research designs, which involve formal modelling, historical analysis, comparative method, statistical tests, and computational simulations.

In the sections that follow, I present examples that sustain the aforementioned categories of models and allow for an evaluation of what we have learnt from models of coalition formation and breakdown. Perhaps, in this field one can fully understand how models play various roles in the discipline. In coalition theory in particular, conceptual and quasi-conceptual models are paramount to tailoring understandings of general phenomena without resorting to direct statistical testing. Evidently, extrapolative models are of utter relevance, and I shall also draw attention to the challenges of performing tests, conducting experiments, and measuring variables. Nonetheless, the vast literature on comparative political coalitions reminds us how empirical tests that lack an underlying explanatory model are bound to accumulate knowledge without building firm explanations. This does not mean that researchers should resign from testing, but rather that formal models are necessary to confer meaning to statistical findings.

After the introduction, the paper is divided into four sections. The first section introduces conceptual models in coalition theory, highlighting their centrality to the foundations of the theoretical endeavour in this literature. In the second section, I discuss the role played by quasi-conceptual models in tailoring explanations of empirical regularities observed in real-world coalitions, such as Gamson’s conjecture. The third section focuses on extrapolative models of coalition formation and breakdown, which are paramount to the empirical testing of hypotheses. An assessment section follows suit, and I thereby summarise the taxonomy of formal models in coalition theory.

CONCEPTUAL MODELS: SETTING THE FOUNDATIONS OF COALITION THEORY[up]

The roots of coalition theory can be traced back to the seminal works by John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern, and Lloyd Shapley, who developed the conceptual models that allowed Riker to design his minimal-winning coalition model. Coalitions are the outcome of bargaining processes that are productively represented by the tools of game theory. In the Theory of Games and Economic Behaviour ( ‍Von Neumann, John and Oskar Morgenstern. 1953. Theory of Games and Economic Behaviour. Princeton: Princeton University Press.1953), von Neumann and Morgenstern set the ground for Shapley’s model, which, according to Roth, “summarize[s] the complex possibilities facing each player in a game in characteristic function form by a single number representing the ‘value’ of playing the game” ( ‍Roth, Alvin E. 1988. “Introduction to the Shapley Value”, in Alvin E. Roth (ed.), The Shapley Value: Essays in Honor of Lloyd S. Shapley. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511528446.002.1988: 4).

The simplicity of Shapley’s (or Shapley-Shubik value, in its further developments) model rests on the fact that with three straightforward axioms, one can reach a formula that allows to evaluate an actor’s centrality in a coalition: “Our definition of the power of an individual member depends on the chance he has of being critical to the success of a winning coalition” ( ‍Shapley, Lloyd S. and Martin Shubik. 1988. “A Method for Evaluating the Distribution of Power in a Committee System”, in Alvin E. Roth (ed.), The Shapley Value: Essays in Honor of Lloyd S. Shapley. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511528446.004.Shapley and Shubik, 1988: 41). As general as it is, the model offers a concept applicable to any situation where one needs to determine the power of an actor. Some general results of coalition profiles in congress chambers and the United Nations Security Council illustrate how the Shapley-Shubik value is central to the understanding of coalition formation and functioning.

This conceptual model of coalition theory has set the foundations for later developments in the theory. The Shapley-Shubik value served primarily as a ground-breaking model upon which other scholars not only tested its explanatory power, but also derived hypotheses that have been scrutinised in further research projects. Riker ( ‍Riker, William H. 1962. The Theory of Political Coalitions. New Haven: Yale University Press.1962), for instance, devised his concept of minimum-winning coalition based on Shapley’s model. Clearly, in this case, a conceptual model was essential to set a new research agenda, which produced other models of different natures. To be sure, conceptual models allow for the derivation of empirically testable hypotheses, although they by themselves are not supposed to be directly tested.

To the extent that conceptual models set research agendas and the theoretical/epistemological lenses through which researchers analyse political phenomena, they play the fundamental role of drawing scholars’ attention to quintessential elements of these very phenomena. In the case of coalition theory, the Shapley-Shubik value has defined the importance of pivotal actors in coalition formation and functioning. The conceptual leap to Riker’s model is direct and clear. Nevertheless, conceptual models in coalition theory were not capable of explaining regularities in real-world coalitions, nor they were prone to testing in more complex settings. Even Riker’s model was subjected to criticism for its inability to explain why disequilibrium in coalition formation and maintenance occurred, especially when comparing across multiples cases ( ‍Dowding, Keith. 1995. “Interpreting Formal Coalition Theory”, in Keith Dowding and Desmond King (eds.), Preferences, Institutions, and Rational Choice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Dowding, 1995). Therefore, conceptual models of coalition do not suffice to offer overarching explanations, opening a window of opportunity for other approaches to modelling.

QUASI-CONCEPTUAL MODELS OF COALITION FORMATION: EXPLAINING REGULARITIES[up]

In political science, scholars are frequently faced with patterns in real-world phenomena. The existence of patterns suggests that some sort of mechanism must be at operation. Ideally, political scientists would propose descriptions of the mechanism, further testing them in order to explain the phenomena. Nevertheless, across political science one may find various examples of patterns which are known to exist (due to empirical evidence), but which are not fully described as part of a theoretical endeavour. In coalition theory, Gamson’s law —which states that governments distribute portfolios in proportion to each party’s contribution of seats to the coalition ( ‍Carroll, Royce and Gary W. Cox. 2007. “The Logic of Gamson’s Law: Pre-election Coalitions and Portfolio Allocations”, American Journal of Political Science, 51 (2): 300-‍313. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2007.00252.x.Carroll and Cox, 2007;  ‍Gamson, William. 1961. “A Theory of Coalition Formation”, American Sociological Review, 26 (3): 373-‍382. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2090664.Gamson, 1961)— illustrates the case of an empirical regularity lacking an explanatory mechanism.

This sort of epistemological problem has led coalition modellers to devise quasi-conceptual models. This type of model is designed to explain an observed empirical regularity by resorting to mathematical deductions. Data come first and the model explains their patterns by unravelling potential explanatory mechanisms. To illustrate quasi-conceptual models, I shall present two different ones in coalition theory, showing how the literature uses logic and mathematical tools to enhance arguments and tailor explanations about coalition formation and breakdown.

In a recent article, Michael Laver and Kenneth Benoit ( ‍Laver, Michael and Kenneth Benoit. 2015. “The Basic Arithmetic of Legislative Decisions”, American Journal of Political Science, 59 (2): 275-‍291. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/ajps.12111.2015) develop a model-cum-typology of party systems that account for the variations of coalition governments observed in 29 European parliamentary democracies. They call this classification “the basic arithmetic of legislative decisions”, for it represents the possible outcomes of the electoral process that lead parties to power; and the outcomes of the bargaining process within the legislature. Table 1 displays their typology.

Table 1.

Universe of possible legislative party systems

Single winning party No single winning party
S 1 ≥ W S 1 < W
S 1 + S 2 ≥ W S 1 + S 2 < W
S 1 + S 3 ≥ W S 1 + S 3 < W
S 2 + S 3 < W S 2 + S 3 ≥ W
Single winning party Strongly dominant party Top-three Top-two Open

Source: Adapted from Laver and Benoit ( ‍Laver, Michael and Kenneth Benoit. 2015. “The Basic Arithmetic of Legislative Decisions”, American Journal of Political Science, 59 (2): 275-‍291. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/ajps.12111.2015: 277). Notation: Siis legislative party i (varying from one to three parties in this case) and W is the winning quota to successfully pass proposals. Laver and Benoit (ibid.) limit their example to three parties, but the same logic applies for n parties.

The classification in Table 1 represents different scenarios under which coalitions can form. It is not simply a classification per se, because Laver and Benoit ( ‍Laver, Michael and Kenneth Benoit. 2015. “The Basic Arithmetic of Legislative Decisions”, American Journal of Political Science, 59 (2): 275-‍291. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/ajps.12111.2015) consider the implications of simple logical statements to draw conclusions about how coalitions should form. Those implications are not derived in a game-theoretical fashion, but they still resort to basic mathematical tools and numerical examples to prove the argument and sustain the model. Once their model-cum-typology is presented, Laver and Benoit (ibid.) proceed to analyse the empirical distribution of those classes of party systems across their dataset of European democracies. Furthermore, they also resort to multinomial logistic regression to estimate the level of change of each legislative type in face of changes in seat shares. Essentially, their model attempts to provide conceptual grounds to describe and explain regularities observed in European parliaments and estimate coalition change of each type.

Anna Bassi ( ‍Bassi, Anna. 2013. “A Model of Endogenous Government Formation”, American Journal of Political Science, 57 (4): 777-‍793. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/ajps.12031.2013) follows a similar procedure in her works on government formation. Bassi is concerned about what she calls a “prominent empirical regularity”: “the share of cabinet portfolios that each government party receives is almost perfectly proportional to the share of legislative seats it contributes to the government […], with no evidence of a formateur advantage even when portfolio payoffs are weighed by salience” (ibid.: 777). Departing from that evidence, which sustains Gamson’s conjecture of proportional portfolio allocation, she develops a game-theoretical model that “makes predictions in line with Gamson’s Law” (ibid.: 778). Essentially, her bargaining model determines endogenously the role of the formateur, and it follows four stages of bargaining, which are solved for equilibrium via backward induction. A similar effort to solve the puzzle of Gamson’s law has been systematically conducted by Indridi Indridason ( ‍Indrason, Indridi H. 2015. “Live for Today, Hope for Tomorrow? Rethinking Gamson’s Law”. Work in Progress. Available at: Available at: https://bit.ly/2TgdHOT.2015), who has developed a game-theoretical approach coupled with empirical testing to tailor explanations to the puzzle.

Both models depart from empirical regularities to solve a theoretical puzzle in the literature. A great deal of the literature on coalition theory has developed upon the failures of previous models that could not account for specific phenomena in the real world. Even Riker’s initial theory was subjected to criticisms for the lack of predictive power, especially when confronted with empirical data

Riker’s model was a simple implementation of the Shapley-Shubik value to determine the minimal-winning coalition. It was institution-free and, therefore, could not account for the variation observed in real world cases. Many counter-examples contradicted his theory on the surface, if one cares about folk predictions. However, Riker’s model showed that coalition formation is not a random nor obvious process, which is a prediction of the type-level (i.e., a prediction about a general phenomenon). By devising the minimal-winning coalition concept, Riker identified a rationale for government formation and breakdown, which allowed for further theoretical and empirical developments.

‍[3]
. However, these failures have led researchers to explore the causes and mechanisms of the divergence between models and the real-world. In Bassi’s and Laver and Benoit’s cases, the models offer explanations of certain regularities in data, connecting the dots through mathematical expressions, implications and propositions. Without the models, we would only be able to observe patterns in data; perhaps, some statistical tests would be capable of correctly predicting phenomena of their interest based upon recurring patterns, but we would not be able to tell the difference between a good and a bad prediction because an underlying explanatory mechanism would be missing. In this sense, the value of their models resides in the explanatory nature and how they give meaning to observed patterns. In other words, they accommodate data into an overarching quasi-conceptual model.

In order to make this point clearer, it is worth mentioning the example of conservation laws in physics. Scientists have always known that some physical quantities obey conservation laws — Isaac Newton’s classical mechanics is based upon the notion that momentum is always conserved. Energy conservation was an essential part of thermodynamics and it had been validated by countless empirical evidence and tests ( ‍Kuhn, Thomas S. 1977. “Energy Conservation as an Example of Simultaneous Discovery”, in Thomas S. Kuhn (ed.), The Essential Tension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226217239.001.0001.Kuhn, 1977). Nevertheless, a mathematical model capable of explaining why some quantities are always conserved was still absent until the beginning of the 20th century. In 1915 and 1918, mathematician Emmy Noether deduced a mathematical model that proved the connection between conservation laws and symmetries, a feat of such importance to physics that Nina Bayer ( ‍Bayer, Nina. 1999. “The Heritage of Emmy Noether in Algebra, Geometry, and Physics”. Israel Mathematical Conference Proceedings, vol. 12, 20 September 2017. Available at: Available at: https://bit.ly/2VmoXGZ.1999) sums up in the following terms: “They [Noether’s theorems] led to a deeper understanding of laws such as the principles of conservation of energy, angular momentum, etc., and also were instrumental in the great discoveries of gauge field symmetries of the 20th century”. Empirical evidence was finally connected with a formal, explanatory model that bridged two distinct domains in physics and mathematics.

The aforementioned coalition models are analogous to Noether’s theorem: they have been designed to provide explanations of regularities observed in the real world, but which lacked an explanatory mechanism. They are quasi-conceptual because their goal consists in providing explanations to patterns in data rather than solely testing them or advancing a theoretical argument. Daniela Giannetti and Itai Sened’s ( ‍Giannetti, Daniela and Itai Sened. 2004. “Party Competition and Coalition Formation”, Journal of Theoretical Politics, 16 (4): 483-‍515. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/0951629804046151.2004) coalition model of the Italian parliament follows similar lines, with a particular way of connecting the model’s predictions with empirical data. They resort to visual tools (mostly graphs of left-right vs institutional dimensions) to locate parties and coalitions throughout Italian history, relating their positions in the two-dimensional space to predictions in the model. They do so because they express doubts about the prospects of using statistical tests (namely, regression) to validate models. Giannetti and Sened affirm:

An important part of the failure to use mathematical models in the analysis of real-life politics stems from an undue loyalty to traditional quantitative statistical analysis in the study of politics. Regression analysis in whatever form is unlikely to help much in analysing such complex environments as multiparty parliamentary systems. The abstract mathematical models of this reality make it succinctly clear (ibid.: 513).

I would not make such a strong statement, for there are prospects for combining statistics and formal models ( ‍Ansolabehere, Stephen, James M. Snyder Jr., Aaron B. Strauss and Michael M. Ting. 2005. “Voting Weights and Formateur Advantages in the Formation of Coalition Governments”, American Journal of Political Science, 49 (3): 550-‍563. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2005.00141.x.Ansolabehere et al., 2005;  ‍Signorino, Curtis S. 1999. “Strategic Interaction and the Statistical Analysis of International Conflict”, American Political Science Review, 93 (2): 279-‍297. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2585396.Signorino, 1999,  ‍Signorino, Curtis S. 2003. “Structure and Uncertainty in Discrete Choice Models”, Political Analysis, 11(4): 316-‍344. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1093/pan/mpg020.2003). Furthermore, researchers might be interested in testing the outcomes of a given model, rather than the underlying assumptions and structure. This is a methodological decision, which does not necessarily end in failure. In the next section, I shall turn to coalition models that are tested via statistics.

TESTING COALITION MODELS[up]

The bulk of the literature in coalition theory is empirically-oriented, and much of this orientation assumes the form of statistical tests and models. Since the publication of Riker’s model, political scientists have been testing his predictions, as well as other models’ predictions, via statistics and computational simulations.

Laver and Shepsle ( ‍Laver, Michael and Kenneth Shepsle. 1996. Making and Breaking Governments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625671.1996) made an important contribution to the testing of coalition models by developing their own model and conducting a computational simulation to validate its structure before fitting empirical data into it. The underlying assumption in their model consists in shifting the attention to the allocation of ministries to explain government formation (and breakdown). Laver and Shepsle state:

For us, then, a government consists of an allocation of authority in particular policy jurisdictions to particular political parties with well-known policy representations in the areas. Because there is only a handful of key policy jurisdictions and only a limited number of parties with ministerial-calibre politicians who can credibly be nominated to these, the numbers of different potential cabinets is also limited. Thus, government policy outputs are selected from a finite set of policy forecasts, each forecast being associated with a particular portfolio allocation. The finite nature of the set of credible potential governments means that the business of building and maintaining a government is explicable […] in a more straightforward manner than the general spatial model suggests (ibid.: 14-15).

The portfolio allocation model is grounded in eight assumptions based upon Rational Choice Theory (henceforth, RCT), and unfolds over three stages. Firstly, a party is selected to form a cabinet, proposing a certain allocation of ministries. If such allocation differs from the status quo, it advances to stage two, where the members of the coalition accept or reject the proposal. If they accept, it proceeds to the third stage, where the cabinet is voted in the chamber; if members reject, it returns to the first stage.

Evidently, there exist variations across parliamentary systems, yet the model is fairly representative of the general procedures in government formation.

‍[4]
In their analysis, two concepts are crucial: the equilibrium cabinet, which “once it is formed, stays formed because no political actor with the ability to act in such as to bring down the cabinet and replace it with some alternative has the incentive to do so” ( ‍Laver, Michael and Kenneth Shepsle. 1996. Making and Breaking Governments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625671.Laver and Shepsle, 1996: 61); and the strong party (S), which “participates in every cabinet preferred by a majority to the cabinet in which Party S takes all portfolios” ( ‍Laver, Michael and Kenneth Shepsle. 1996. Making and Breaking Governments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625671.Laver and Shepsle, 1996: 70). Very strong parties lead to the formation of equilibrium parties, because it has the ability to shift the bargaining closer to its ideal point

In their analysis, the authors conclude: “[A] powerful position in the decisive structure enhances a party’s control over the making and breaking of governments in two ways. First, a more dominant position in the decisive structure is far more likely to make a party strong, and hence an essential member of any government. Second, while even parties with weaker positions in the decisive structure can be strong if they occupy the right position in the configuration of party positions, dominant parties are far more likely than these to be very strong, and thus not to have to rely on their ability to win standoffs” (

Laver, Michael and Kenneth Shepsle. 1996. Making and Breaking Governments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625671.

Laver and Shepsle, 1996: 105
).

‍[5]
.

The spatial model in Laver and Shepsle ( ‍Laver, Michael and Kenneth Shepsle. 1996. Making and Breaking Governments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625671.1996) was derived using measures of distance in Euclidean space and theorems based on set theory. The authors acknowledge that formal models “yield expressions that, while rigorously derived, do not give us much intuition about what is likely to happen in particular real-world cases” (ibid.: 93), and resort to computational simulation to explore the predictions of their model, specifically “of which factors affect the existence and identity of a strong party” (ibid.: 97).

The portfolio allocation model as developed by Laver and Shepsle is representative of the empirically-oriented works in coalition theory. Formal models are tested via the predictions entailed in their theorems and propositions. Perhaps, one of the clearest examples of this approach is the seminal paper on government formation by Lanny Martin and Randolph Stevenson ( ‍Martin, Lanny W. and Randolph T. Stevenson. 2001. “Government Formation in Parliamentary Democracies”, American Journal of Political Science, 45 (1): 33-‍50. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2669358.2001), where the authors derive 21 hypotheses from coalition models and subject them to a test of maximum-likelihood estimation (MLE). They select MLE because it “allows the researcher to choose a distribution for the dependent variable that is appropriate to the true form of that variable” (ibid.: 38), which is an important concern if one wants to perform a test that adequately represents the structure of the formal model. Many other researchers follow the same lines: Volden and Carrubba ( ‍Volden, Craig and Clifford J. Carrubba. 2004. “The Formation of Oversized Coalitions in Parliamentary Democracies”, American Journal of Political Science, 48 (3): 521-‍537. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0092-5853.2004.00085.x.2004) derive a series of variables to test five coalitions models (including their own) using time-series cross-sectional analysis of a dichotomous dependent variable; Diermeier and Merlo ( ‍Diermeier, Daniel and Antonio Merlo. (2004). “An empirical investigation of coalitional bargaining procedures”, Journal of Public Economics, 88 (3-‍4): 783-‍797. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1016/S0047-2727(03)00035-5.2004) test for different bargaining procedures that are frequently assumed in formal models; Martin and Stevenson ( ‍Martin, Lanny W. and Randolph T. Stevenson. 2010. “The Conditional Impact of Incumbency on Government Formation”, American Political Science Review, 104 (3): 503-‍518. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055410000213.2010) use the conditional logit model to test for the impact of incumbency in government formation; Becher and Christiansen (2015) develop a formal model of dissolution threats issued by the prime minister and their effects in legislative bargaining, resorting to content analysis to measure the threats, and then combining the measurements with public opinion and legislative data in standard logit regressions.

Alternative empirical tests of formal models can derive statistical measures directly from the structure of the mathematical component of the model. This the case presented in Ansolabehere et al. ( ‍Ansolabehere, Stephen, James M. Snyder Jr., Aaron B. Strauss and Michael M. Ting. 2005. “Voting Weights and Formateur Advantages in the Formation of Coalition Governments”, American Journal of Political Science, 49 (3): 550-‍563. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2005.00141.x.2005), where the authors identify a misspecification problem in the literature. According to them, the bulk of tests of coalition models uses the number of seats as a measure, but the formal models to which they refer are derived from assumptions on voting weights. As they state:

Voting weights complicate empirical testing of these models. Seat shares do not equal voting weight share, and (…) the approximation can be quite poor. As a result, regression analyses relating seat shares to shares of posts, as done in most empirical work on this topic, will generally yield biased estimates of the relationship between voting weights and cabinet posts. The estimated coefficients of other variables, such as an indicator of the formateur, will also be affected ( ‍Ansolabehere, Stephen, James M. Snyder Jr., Aaron B. Strauss and Michael M. Ting. 2005. “Voting Weights and Formateur Advantages in the Formation of Coalition Governments”, American Journal of Political Science, 49 (3): 550-‍563. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2005.00141.x.Ansolabehere et al., 2005: 552).

These considerations are important not only to their model, but also to the tailoring of explanations and conclusions from the empirical test. The authors, thus, propose a model where the costs and voting weights can be regressed. They do so, because “the appropriate independent variable that measures a party’s bargaining strength is its share of the voting weight in the legislature” (ibid.: 554). It is worth noting that this is one among many other possible specifications to the problem. The authors are aware of that and the implications of other specifications, but they have chosen this particular one because they were able to estimate the model. This a crucial issue, since models (whether purely mathematical or statistical) are constrained by their tractability and solvability ( ‍Signorino, Curtis S. 2003. “Structure and Uncertainty in Discrete Choice Models”, Political Analysis, 11(4): 316-‍344. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1093/pan/mpg020.Signorino, 2003)

This is particularly true of phenomena pervaded with nonlinearities, which in politics take the form of uncertainties. These uncertainties, once represented in a formal model, may produce divergent solutions, depending on how they manifest themselves in the process of solving for the model.

‍[6]
.

Despite such innovativeness, the literature still follows the standard approach of generating hypotheses from models’ theorems and testing them independently from the structure. Hanna Bäck and Patrick Dumont ( ‍Bäck, Hannah and Patrick Dumont. 2008. “Making the First Move”, Public Choice, 135 (3-‍4): 353-‍373. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-007-9267-52008), in designing their two-stage model of the role of the formateur in government formation, provide a compelling argument about why the structural approach might be difficult to represent. The authors state:

Optimally we would like to statistically model the two stages as interdependent, e.g., using a similar approach of analyzing strategic interaction as presented by Signorino ( ‍Signorino, Curtis S. 1999. “Strategic Interaction and the Statistical Analysis of International Conflict”, American Political Science Review, 93 (2): 279-‍297. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2585396.1999). Problems of application in this setting however abound: first, we are here dealing with a two-stage game where one actor (e.g., the Head of State) is making a choice in the 1st stage, and another actor (the formateur) is then interacting with other actors (the other parties); second, we are dealing with a large number of choice alternatives, and the number of choices vary across formation opportunities; finally, we are here dealing with some theories that make multiple equilibrium predictions, which makes it difficult to assign probabilities over outcomes ( ‍Signorino, Curtis S. 1999. “Strategic Interaction and the Statistical Analysis of International Conflict”, American Political Science Review, 93 (2): 279-‍297. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2585396.Signorino 1999, p. 294). An alternative statistical approach would be to use some sort of nested model, which would allow for sequential choices ( ‍Bäck, Hannah and Patrick Dumont. 2008. “Making the First Move”, Public Choice, 135 (3-‍4): 353-‍373. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-007-9267-5Bäck and Dumont, 2008: 360-‍361).

As we can see, deriving a test that respects the structure of the original formal model is not an easy task. Nevertheless, this is a matter of uttermost importance for the validation of empirical tests and their conclusions. Explanation rests on the mathematical derivations entailed in the model, for they provide the links between the operating mechanisms of a particular phenomenon. Furthermore, from the same model different researchers might generate different hypotheses, but telling which one is true to the model is a matter that can only be settled by referring to the structure. If the test is poorly connected to the structure, then settling the case becomes much harder. Therefore, building this connection — for example, via appropriate derivation of equations (see  ‍Signorino, Curtis S. 2003. “Structure and Uncertainty in Discrete Choice Models”, Political Analysis, 11(4): 316-‍344. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1093/pan/mpg020.Signorino, 2003) or measurements ( ‍Ansolabehere, Stephen, James M. Snyder Jr., Aaron B. Strauss and Michael M. Ting. 2005. “Voting Weights and Formateur Advantages in the Formation of Coalition Governments”, American Journal of Political Science, 49 (3): 550-‍563. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2005.00141.x.Ansolabehere et al., 2005) — is essential to enhance explanations and conclusions.

ASSESSMENT[up]

Writing in their seminal book Games and Decisions ( ‍Luce, Robert Duncan and Howard Raiffa. 1957. Games and Decisions: Introduction and Critical Survey. Mineola: Dover Publications.1957), Robert Luce and Howard Raiffa addressed the challenges that coalition studies would face as part of the conceptual and empirical features of coalitions. As a game that is played by n actors, it is only natural that the level of complexity entailed in a model is far higher than that of a two-person game. The authors suggest:

A major obstacle to developing a satisfactory theory of coalition formation is that in the present formalizations of a game no explicit provisions are made about communication and collusion among the players […]. Thus any theory of collusion, i.e., of coalition formation, has a distinctly ad hoc flavour. The difficulties in making assumptions about communication appear, at least superficially, to stem from the variety of rules which are found in empirical situations. […]. In addition to the conceptual complications of collusion, there are inherent practical complications as n gets larger, for the number of possible coalitions increases at a fantastic rate; the difficulty of a detailed analysis of a two-person game such as chess is minor compared to a similar analysis of most n-person games. One of the principal features of the current theory is to bypass such a detailed analysis. That we can successfully avoid combinatorial problems at the conceptual level does not necessarily mean that we can do so when dealing with empirical situations ( ‍Luce, Robert Duncan and Howard Raiffa. 1957. Games and Decisions: Introduction and Critical Survey. Mineola: Dover Publications.Luce and Raiffa, 1957: 156).

Since then, we have walked a long path of modelling and testing. Even though the specificity of many studies seems to confirm the aforementioned ad hoc character of the literature on coalition theory, this is an impression limited to the surface of the theoretical and empirical advances in the field. The difficulties posed by a n-player game have been tackled through the theoretical and methodological lenses within specific institutional settings. The rules of the game eliminate combinatorial problems that would render coalition models intractable. Furthermore, thanks to an enormous collective effort to collect, systematically organise and test data, researchers can tailor their models to explain observable patterns and derive their hypotheses.

The three classes of models presented above reflect the lessons learned since the publication of Riker’s book. Conceptual models have set the theoretical grounds that allowed for the development of empirical tests —not to mention data collection— and have led to a better understanding of the boundaries of explanation in coalition theory. Regularities in data which lack explanatory mechanisms have extensively benefited from quasi-conceptual models. Last, but not least, statistical tests have played an important role in assessing coalition models’ predictions. All these models combined constitute the edifice of coalition theory.

However, when it comes to testing formal models in coalition theory, one important challenge still remains: how should modellers and empiricists alike connect the mathematical part of the formal model and the statistical test? This issue has been recently placed under scrutiny by Signorino and his colleagues, who have developed solutions to the problem of structural consistency between formal model and statistical test. Bridging both sides of the same problem demands returning to the original deductions entailed in the mathematical model and statistical equations, connecting them via mathematical tools such as Taylor series, numerics etc. Evidently, this is a particular set of solutions which requires specific training, meaning that the bulk of empirical testing will probably follow the path of deriving hypotheses from a model’s outcomes and testing them via classical statistical tests.

Nonetheless, the taxonomy hereby proposed reveals the relevance of mathematical models —and rational choice models, in particular— to political science, which is of uttermost importance if one considers the misunderstandings and prejudices against RCT. To be sure, after the publication of Donald Green and Ian Shapiro’s critique ( ‍Green, Donald and Ian Shapiro. 1994. Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory. New Haven: Yale University Press.1994), many scholars have echoed criticisms against the explanatory potential of rational choice models. Some have argued that rational choice theorists were plotting against other methodological approaches, attempting to confer a hegemonic status on RCT ( ‍Becker, Gary S. 1976. The Economic Approach to Human Behavior. Chicago, Chicago University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226217062.001.0001.Becker, 1976). Others have suggested, following Green and Shapiro ( ‍Green, Donald and Ian Shapiro. 1994. Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory. New Haven: Yale University Press.1994), that rational choice models are intrinsically trivial, failing to explain various cases and political phenomena. Although some of those criticisms might be true of certain rational choice models, it is rather a generalisation that fails to understand the diversity of rational choice approaches ( ‍Cox, Gary. 1999. “The Empirical Content of Rational Choice Theory: A Reply to Green and Shapiro”, Journal of Theoretical Politics, 11 (2): 147-‍169. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/0951692899011002001.Cox, 1999,  ‍Cox, Gary. 2004. “Lies, Damned Lies, and Rational Choice Analyses”, in Ian Shapiro, Roger M. Smith and Tarek E. Masoud (eds.), Problems and Methods in the Study of Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511492174.008.2004;  ‍Dowding, Keith. 1995. “Interpreting Formal Coalition Theory”, in Keith Dowding and Desmond King (eds.), Preferences, Institutions, and Rational Choice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Dowding, 1995,  ‍Dowding, Keith. 2005. “Is it Rational to Vote? Five Types of Answer and a Suggestion”, British Journal of Politics and International Relations, 7 (3): 442-‍459. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-856X.2005.00188.x.2005,  ‍Dowding, Keith. 2016. The Philosophy and Methods of Political Science. London: Palgrave.2016;  ‍Hindmoor, Andrew and Brad Taylor. 2015. Rational Choice. London: Palgrave. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-137-42744-1.Hindmoor and Taylor, 2015;  ‍Morton, Rebecca M. 1999. Methods and Models: A Guide to the Empirical Analysis of Formal Models in Political Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511612473.Morton, 1999), not to mention the current declining presence of formal models in the pages of top-tier journals ( ‍Jacoby, William G., Robert N. Lupton, Miles T. Armaly and Adam Enders. 2017. “Report to the Editorial Board and the Midwest Political Science Association Executive Council”. Available at: Available at: https://bit.ly/2HRHUKq.Jacoby et al., 2017;  ‍Ishiyama, John. 2015. “Report of the Editors of the American Political Science Review, 2013-‍14”, PS: Political Science and and Politics, 48 (2): 400-‍403. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S1049096515000037.Ishiyama, 2015;  ‍Norris, Pippa. 1997. “Toward A More Cosmopolitan Political Science?”, European Journal of Political Research, 31 (1): 17-‍34. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/1475-6765.00301.Norris, 1997). In this sense, the explanation-oriented taxonomy of rational models offers a more nuanced understanding of modelling and models, and their relevance to the discipline.

Among many things, coalition theory has taught us that formal models serve distinct purposes, each of which answering its own set of research questions. The existence of the aforementioned classes of models —which is just one among others that could be tailored to classify models— contradicts the discourse that labels models as fables or parables ( ‍Cartwright, Nancy. 2010. “Models: Parables v Fables”, in Roman Frigg and Matthew Hunter (eds.), Beyond Mimesis and Convention: Representation in Art and Science. Amsterdam: Springer Netherlands. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3851-7_2.Cartwright, 2010;  ‍Rubinstein, Ariel. 2012. Economic Fables. Cambridge: Open Book Publishers. Available at: https://doi.org/10.11647/OBP.0020.Rubinstein, 2012). Models as fables might be comparable to conceptual models, but not all models are solely concerned with concepts, paradoxes and other theoretical issues. In coalition theory, models play all three roles that I have identified, and each shape the research agenda in their own respect. In doing so, they contribute to the accumulation of knowledge in coalition behaviour and the development of the field as a whole. Table 2 summarises the main ideas advanced by the aforementioned taxonomy of models.

Table 2.

Taxonomy of models

Type Description Examples
Conceptual These models advance concepts and predictions via mathematical expressions derived from set theory and game theory. They are not empirically testable, yet their predictions offer logical explanations about general phenomena. Lloyd Shapley ( ‍Shapley, Lloyd S. 1988. “A Value for N-Person Games”, in Alvin E. Roth (ed.), The Shapley Value: Essays in Honor of Lloyd S. Shapley. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511528446.003.1988)
Richard D. McKelvey ( ‍McKelvey, Richard D. 1976. “Intransitivities in Multidimensional Voting Models and Some Implications for Agenda Control”, Journal of Economic Theory, 12 (3): 472-‍482.1976)
Norman Schoffield ( ‍Schoffield, Norman. 1978. “Instability of Simple Dynamic Games”, The Review of Economic Studies, 45 (3): 575-‍594. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2297259.1978)
Quasi-conceptual The model explains an observed empirical regularity by resorting to mathematical deductions. Data come first and the model explains their patterns. Anna Bassi ( ‍Bassi, Anna. 2013. “A Model of Endogenous Government Formation”, American Journal of Political Science, 57 (4): 777-‍793. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/ajps.12031.2013)
Daniella Giannetti and Itai Sened ( ‍Giannetti, Daniela and Itai Sened. 2004. “Party Competition and Coalition Formation”, Journal of Theoretical Politics, 16 (4): 483-‍515. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/0951629804046151.2004)
Indridi Indrason ( ‍Indrason, Indridi H. 2015. “Live for Today, Hope for Tomorrow? Rethinking Gamson’s Law”. Work in Progress. Available at: Available at: https://bit.ly/2TgdHOT.2015)
Michael Laver and Kenneth Benoit ( ‍Laver, Michael and Kenneth Benoit. 2015. “The Basic Arithmetic of Legislative Decisions”, American Journal of Political Science, 59 (2): 275-‍291. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/ajps.12111.2015)

Extrapolative
Data-fit Mathematical model and statistical test are not structurally linked via mathematical expressions. Hypotheses are formulated based on the model’s propositions and theorems, and then subject to an appropriate statistical test. Craig Volden and Clifford Carrubba ( ‍Volden, Craig and Clifford J. Carrubba. 2004. “The Formation of Oversized Coalitions in Parliamentary Democracies”, American Journal of Political Science, 48 (3): 521-‍537. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0092-5853.2004.00085.x.2004)
Hanna Bäck and Patrick Dumont ( ‍Bäck, Hannah and Patrick Dumont. 2008. “Making the First Move”, Public Choice, 135 (3-‍4): 353-‍373. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-007-9267-52008)
Lanny Martin and Randolph Stevenson ( ‍Martin, Lanny W. and Randolph T. Stevenson. 2001. “Government Formation in Parliamentary Democracies”, American Journal of Political Science, 45 (1): 33-‍50. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2669358.2001)
Michael Laver and Kenneth Shepsle ( ‍Laver, Michael and Kenneth Shepsle. 1996. Making and Breaking Governments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625671.1996)
Mathematical-statistical Statistical tests are derived directly from the mathematical model. In this case, the test represents the details of the model. There is a structural, mathematical link between the formal model and the statistical test. Stephen Ansolabehere et al. ( ‍Ansolabehere, Stephen, James M. Snyder Jr., Aaron B. Strauss and Michael M. Ting. 2005. “Voting Weights and Formateur Advantages in the Formation of Coalition Governments”, American Journal of Political Science, 49 (3): 550-‍563. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2005.00141.x.2005)

Source: The author’ own elabotarion.

Note: The examples provided here refer only to coalition theory. The classification, however, can be extended to other models.

Nevertheless, there are still challenges to be faced. As mentioned previously, addressing the structural settings of models is an issue of uttermost importance, which may enhance the explanatory capabilities of empirical tests. Yet this requires political scientists to combine efforts to devise appropriate mathematical-statistical links between model and test, not to mention measurements, which are an integral part of model testing. Measuring the correct variables in the model guarantees that the test is true to the mathematics, and it is itself a challenge. Our measurements are based upon data available, and on our interpretations of what they mean to the model and statistical test. However, they may prove to be incorrect, inaccurate or imprecise, as shown in the case of voting weights. Therefore, extra efforts to improve measurements constitute an important challenge in coalition theory. Nonetheless, by being aware of these methodological issues, we might be able to work on inventive ways for collecting appropriate data and building the necessary bridges between model and test.

CONCLUSION[up]

Since the publication of Riker’s work back in 1962, the field of coalition theory has thrived and now constitutes one of the main research areas in political science. Throughout the development of the field, RC models played an important role in tailoring explanations and generating predictions about a variety of phenomena involving coalition formation and breakdown. These models shed light on the connections between agents, institutional rules and political contexts, offering insightful perspectives about the dynamics of coalitions.

Throughout this article, I have surveyed examples of coalition models attempting to show how they serve different purposes when building explanations. In spite of the fact that the literature (opponents of models included) has tended to think of the predictability of a model solely in terms of empirical tests, models can come in distinct flavours, offering predictions in the conceptual level; unravelling the explanatory and predictive mechanisms underlying regularities; and extrapolating the mathematical expressions to fit data or derive statistical tests. All these types share the essential characteristic of models, i.e., predictability. After all, models are designed to generate predictions and explanations, and that should be the currency to judge their success. The question here is that prediction should not be restricted to the results of an empirical test, especially when it resorts to data-fit techniques.

The field of coalition theory is prolific, and knowledge is still under construction in this literature. Recent works on the complexity of the coalition game have drawn attention to a myriad variables, such as verticalization of political alignments in different territorial levels (i.e., national and subnational), and nationalization of political parties ( ‍Albala, Adrián. 2018. “The missing piece: Introducing the 4th generation of coalition theories”, in Adrián Albala and Josep Maria Reniu (eds.), Coalition Politics and Federalism. Amsterdam: Springer. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-75100-9_2.Albala, 2018). By examining how coalition bargaining may take place in a feedback process between different layers of political competition, this literature has the potential to offer ground-breaking insights on government formation, maintenance and breakdown. In this context, formal models may provide an invaluable aid in tailoring explanations to the aforementioned phenomena, especially mathematical-statistical models for they are well suited to incorporate the nonlinearities entailed in such complex, iterative, multilayered phenomena.

Coalition theory, as one can see, is a lively field where researchers have been generating a variety of explanations and predictions, resorting in this process to a myriad methodological approaches. It is only natural that models will play a fundamental role in the new generation of coalition explanations. The taxonomy presented here can help us understand the various types of models and the predictions they generate, which is quintessential to judging their explanatory power and to designing the appropriate model for each type of phenomena. With all this theoretical and methodological arsenal at hand, we can only expect coalition theory to thrive further in the years to come.

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS[up]

I would like to thank Prof. Keith Dowding (Australian National University), Prof. Patrick Dumont (Australian National University), and Dr. Ivette Carrascal (UNILAB-Malês) for their invaluable comments on the first version of this paper. I would also like to thank the anonymous reviewers for their feedback on this work.

Notes[up]

[1]

Throughout the paper, I will focus my attention on recent models of coalition theory. Seminal works in this literature include: Axelrod’s ( ‍Axelrod, Robert M. 1984. The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books.1984, chapters 1 and 8) works on cooperation and strategic, long-term interaction; Dodd’s ( ‍Dodd, Lawrence. 1976. Coalitions in Parliamentary Government. Princeton: Princeton University Press.1976) game-theoretical approach to cabinet durability; De Swann’s ( ‍De Swann, Abram. 1973. Coalition Theories and Cabinet Formations. Amsterdam: Elsevier.1973) results of formal modelling and statistical testing, and the implications of combining both strategies for coalition theory. For a comprehensive introduction, see Müller et al. ( ‍Müller, Wolfgang C., Torjörn Bergman and Kaare Strøm. 2010. “Coalition theory and cabinet governance”, in Kaare Strøm, Wolfgang C. Müller y Torbjörn Bergman (eds.), Cabinets and Coalition Bargaining. Oxford: Oxford University Press.2010) and Strøm and Nyblade ( ‍Strøm, Kaare and Benjamin Nyblade. 2009. “Coalition Theory and Government Formation”, in Carles Boix y Susan C. Stokes (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.2009).

[2]

Historical institutionalists have also contributed to the theoretical endeavour in coalition theory. By taking a historicist approach to political phenomena, these scholars draw attention to issues of timing and sequencing, and the complex relations between agents and institutions ( ‍Pierson, Paul. 2004. Politics in time. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1515/9781400841080.Pierson, 2004,  ‍Pierson, Paul. 2015. “Power and path dependence”, in James Mahoney y Kathleen Thelen (eds.), Advances in Comparative-Historical Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316273104.006.2015;  ‍Thelen, Kathleen and James Mahoney. 2015. “Comparative-historical analysis in contemporary political science”, in James Mahoney y Kathleen Thelen (eds.), Advances in Comparative-Historical Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316273104.002.Thelen and Mahoney, 2015). In particular, Hacker et al. ( ‍Hacker, Jacob S., Paul Pierson and Kathleen Thelen. 2015. “Drift and conversion: hidden faces of institutional change”, in James Mahoney and Kathleen Thelen (eds.), Advances in Comparative-Historical Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316273104.008.2015) analysis of institutional change via drift or conversion offers an interesting epistemology to understand how coalitions may reinterpret institutions to serve their own ends, in a typical bargaining process.

[3]

Riker’s model was a simple implementation of the Shapley-Shubik value to determine the minimal-winning coalition. It was institution-free and, therefore, could not account for the variation observed in real world cases. Many counter-examples contradicted his theory on the surface, if one cares about folk predictions. However, Riker’s model showed that coalition formation is not a random nor obvious process, which is a prediction of the type-level (i.e., a prediction about a general phenomenon). By devising the minimal-winning coalition concept, Riker identified a rationale for government formation and breakdown, which allowed for further theoretical and empirical developments.

[4]

Evidently, there exist variations across parliamentary systems, yet the model is fairly representative of the general procedures in government formation.

[5]

In their analysis, the authors conclude: “[A] powerful position in the decisive structure enhances a party’s control over the making and breaking of governments in two ways. First, a more dominant position in the decisive structure is far more likely to make a party strong, and hence an essential member of any government. Second, while even parties with weaker positions in the decisive structure can be strong if they occupy the right position in the configuration of party positions, dominant parties are far more likely than these to be very strong, and thus not to have to rely on their ability to win standoffs” ( ‍Laver, Michael and Kenneth Shepsle. 1996. Making and Breaking Governments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625671.Laver and Shepsle, 1996: 105).

[6]

This is particularly true of phenomena pervaded with nonlinearities, which in politics take the form of uncertainties. These uncertainties, once represented in a formal model, may produce divergent solutions, depending on how they manifest themselves in the process of solving for the model.

References[up]

[1] 

Albala, Adrián. 2018. “The missing piece: Introducing the 4th generation of coalition theories”, in Adrián Albala and Josep Maria Reniu (eds.), Coalition Politics and Federalism. Amsterdam: Springer. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-75100-9_2.

[2] 

Ansolabehere, Stephen, James M. Snyder Jr., Aaron B. Strauss and Michael M. Ting. 2005. “Voting Weights and Formateur Advantages in the Formation of Coalition Governments”, American Journal of Political Science, 49 (3): 550-‍563. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2005.00141.x.

[3] 

Axelrod, Robert M. 1984. The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books.

[4] 

Bäck, Hannah and Patrick Dumont. 2008. “Making the First Move”, Public Choice, 135 (3-‍4): 353-‍373. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-007-9267-5

[5] 

Bassi, Anna. 2013. “A Model of Endogenous Government Formation”, American Journal of Political Science, 57 (4): 777-‍793. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/ajps.12031.

[6] 

Bayer, Nina. 1999. “The Heritage of Emmy Noether in Algebra, Geometry, and Physics”. Israel Mathematical Conference Proceedings, vol. 12, 20 September 2017. Available at: Available at: https://bit.ly/2VmoXGZ.

[7] 

Becker, Gary S. 1976. The Economic Approach to Human Behavior. Chicago, Chicago University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226217062.001.0001.

[8] 

Black, Duncan. 1958. The Theory of Committees and Elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

[9] 

Carroll, Royce and Gary W. Cox. 2007. “The Logic of Gamson’s Law: Pre-election Coalitions and Portfolio Allocations”, American Journal of Political Science, 51 (2): 300-‍313. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2007.00252.x.

[10] 

Cartwright, Nancy. 2010. “Models: Parables v Fables”, in Roman Frigg and Matthew Hunter (eds.), Beyond Mimesis and Convention: Representation in Art and Science. Amsterdam: Springer Netherlands. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3851-7_2.

[11] 

Cox, Gary. 1999. “The Empirical Content of Rational Choice Theory: A Reply to Green and Shapiro”, Journal of Theoretical Politics, 11 (2): 147-‍169. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/0951692899011002001.

[12] 

Cox, Gary. 2004. “Lies, Damned Lies, and Rational Choice Analyses”, in Ian Shapiro, Roger M. Smith and Tarek E. Masoud (eds.), Problems and Methods in the Study of Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511492174.008.

[13] 

De Swann, Abram. 1973. Coalition Theories and Cabinet Formations. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

[14] 

Diermeier, Daniel and Antonio Merlo. (2004). “An empirical investigation of coalitional bargaining procedures”, Journal of Public Economics, 88 (3-‍4): 783-‍797. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1016/S0047-2727(03)00035-5.

[15] 

Diermeier, Daniel and Razvan Vlaicu. 2011. “Parties, Coalitions, and the Internal Organization of Legislatures”, American Political Science Review, 105 (2): 359-‍380. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055411000104.

[16] 

Dodd, Lawrence. 1976. Coalitions in Parliamentary Government. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

[17] 

Dowding, Keith. 1995. “Interpreting Formal Coalition Theory”, in Keith Dowding and Desmond King (eds.), Preferences, Institutions, and Rational Choice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

[18] 

Dowding, Keith. 2005. “Is it Rational to Vote? Five Types of Answer and a Suggestion”, British Journal of Politics and International Relations, 7 (3): 442-‍459. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-856X.2005.00188.x.

[19] 

Dowding, Keith. 2016. The Philosophy and Methods of Political Science. London: Palgrave.

[20] 

Dowding, Keith and Desmond King. 1995. “Introduction”, in Keith Dowding and Desmond King, (eds.), Preferences, Institutions, and Rational Choice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

[21] 

Downs, Anthony. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper and Row.

[22] 

Gamson, William. 1961. “A Theory of Coalition Formation”, American Sociological Review, 26 (3): 373-‍382. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2090664.

[23] 

Giannetti, Daniela and Itai Sened. 2004. “Party Competition and Coalition Formation”, Journal of Theoretical Politics, 16 (4): 483-‍515. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/0951629804046151.

[24] 

Green, Donald and Ian Shapiro. 1994. Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory. New Haven: Yale University Press.

[25] 

Hacker, Jacob S., Paul Pierson and Kathleen Thelen. 2015. “Drift and conversion: hidden faces of institutional change”, in James Mahoney and Kathleen Thelen (eds.), Advances in Comparative-Historical Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316273104.008.

[26] 

Hindmoor, Andrew and Brad Taylor. 2015. Rational Choice. London: Palgrave. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-137-42744-1.

[27] 

Hotelling, Harold. 1929. “Stability in Competition”, Economic Journal, 39 (153): 41-‍57. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2224214.

[28] 

Huber, John D. and Cecilia Martinez-Gallardo. 2008. “Replacing Cabinet Ministers: Patterns of Ministerial Stability in Parliamentary Democracies”, American Political Science Review, 102 (2): 169-‍180. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S000305540808012X.

[29] 

Indrason, Indridi H. 2015. “Live for Today, Hope for Tomorrow? Rethinking Gamson’s Law”. Work in Progress. Available at: Available at: https://bit.ly/2TgdHOT.

[30] 

Ishiyama, John. 2015. “Report of the Editors of the American Political Science Review, 2013-‍14”, PS: Political Science and and Politics, 48 (2): 400-‍403. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S1049096515000037.

[31] 

Jacoby, William G., Robert N. Lupton, Miles T. Armaly and Adam Enders. 2017. “Report to the Editorial Board and the Midwest Political Science Association Executive Council”. Available at: Available at: https://bit.ly/2HRHUKq.

[32] 

Kuhn, Thomas S. 1977. “Energy Conservation as an Example of Simultaneous Discovery”, in Thomas S. Kuhn (ed.), The Essential Tension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226217239.001.0001.

[33] 

Laver, Michael and Kenneth Benoit. 2015. “The Basic Arithmetic of Legislative Decisions”, American Journal of Political Science, 59 (2): 275-‍291. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/ajps.12111.

[34] 

Laver, Michael and Kenneth Shepsle. 1996. Making and Breaking Governments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625671.

[35] 

Luce, Robert Duncan and Howard Raiffa. 1957. Games and Decisions: Introduction and Critical Survey. Mineola: Dover Publications.

[36] 

Martin, Lanny W. and Georg Vanberg. 2005. “Coalition Policymaking and Legislative Review”, American Political Science Review, 99 (1): 93-‍106. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055405051518.

[37] 

Martin, Lanny W. and Randolph T. Stevenson. 2001. “Government Formation in Parliamentary Democracies”, American Journal of Political Science, 45 (1): 33-‍50. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2669358.

[38] 

Martin, Lanny W. and Randolph T. Stevenson. 2010. “The Conditional Impact of Incumbency on Government Formation”, American Political Science Review, 104 (3): 503-‍518. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055410000213.

[39] 

McKelvey, Richard D. 1976. “Intransitivities in Multidimensional Voting Models and Some Implications for Agenda Control”, Journal of Economic Theory, 12 (3): 472-‍482.

[40] 

Morton, Rebecca M. 1999. Methods and Models: A Guide to the Empirical Analysis of Formal Models in Political Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511612473.

[41] 

Müller, Wolfgang C., Torjörn Bergman and Kaare Strøm. 2010. “Coalition theory and cabinet governance”, in Kaare Strøm, Wolfgang C. Müller y Torbjörn Bergman (eds.), Cabinets and Coalition Bargaining. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

[42] 

Norris, Pippa. 1997. “Toward A More Cosmopolitan Political Science?”, European Journal of Political Research, 31 (1): 17-‍34. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/1475-6765.00301.

[43] 

Pierson, Paul. 2004. Politics in time. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1515/9781400841080.

[44] 

Pierson, Paul. 2015. “Power and path dependence”, in James Mahoney y Kathleen Thelen (eds.), Advances in Comparative-Historical Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316273104.006.

[45] 

Riker, William H. 1962. The Theory of Political Coalitions. New Haven: Yale University Press.

[46] 

Riker, William H. 1980. “Implications from the Disequilibrium of Majority Rule for the Study of Institutions”, American Political Science Review, 74 (2): 432-‍446.

[47] 

Roth, Alvin E. 1988. “Introduction to the Shapley Value”, in Alvin E. Roth (ed.), The Shapley Value: Essays in Honor of Lloyd S. Shapley. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511528446.002.

[48] 

Rubinstein, Ariel. 2012. Economic Fables. Cambridge: Open Book Publishers. Available at: https://doi.org/10.11647/OBP.0020.

[49] 

Schoffield, Norman. 1978. “Instability of Simple Dynamic Games”, The Review of Economic Studies, 45 (3): 575-‍594. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2297259.

[50] 

Shapley, Lloyd S. 1988. “A Value for N-Person Games”, in Alvin E. Roth (ed.), The Shapley Value: Essays in Honor of Lloyd S. Shapley. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511528446.003.

[51] 

Shapley, Lloyd S. and Martin Shubik. 1988. “A Method for Evaluating the Distribution of Power in a Committee System”, in Alvin E. Roth (ed.), The Shapley Value: Essays in Honor of Lloyd S. Shapley. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511528446.004.

[52] 

Signorino, Curtis S. 1999. “Strategic Interaction and the Statistical Analysis of International Conflict”, American Political Science Review, 93 (2): 279-‍297. Available at: https://doi.org/10.2307/2585396.

[53] 

Signorino, Curtis S. 2003. “Structure and Uncertainty in Discrete Choice Models”, Political Analysis, 11(4): 316-‍344. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1093/pan/mpg020.

[54] 

Strøm, Kaare and Benjamin Nyblade. 2009. “Coalition Theory and Government Formation”, in Carles Boix y Susan C. Stokes (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

[55] 

Thelen, Kathleen and James Mahoney. 2015. “Comparative-historical analysis in contemporary political science”, in James Mahoney y Kathleen Thelen (eds.), Advances in Comparative-Historical Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316273104.002.

[56] 

Volden, Craig and Clifford J. Carrubba. 2004. “The Formation of Oversized Coalitions in Parliamentary Democracies”, American Journal of Political Science, 48 (3): 521-‍537. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.0092-5853.2004.00085.x.

[57] 

Von Neumann, John and Oskar Morgenstern. 1953. Theory of Games and Economic Behaviour. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Biography[up]

[a]

Enzo Lenine Nunes Batista Oliveira Lima holds a PhD in Political Science. He is Professor of International Relations at the University of International Integration of the Afro-Brazilian Lusophony (UNILAB-Malês), Brazil. His research deals primarily with methodology, formal models and rational choice theory, especially with novel forms of modelling political phenomena that take into account nonlinear behaviour. He is also interested in the hierarchies of knowledge in Political Science, having published a paper on this topic in the International Political Science Review.